Blutner/Philosophy of
Mind/Consciousness
The
greatest gift which humanity has received is free choice. It is true that we
are limited in our use of free choice But the little free choice we have is such
a great gift and is potentially worth so much that for this itself life is
worthwhile living. (Isaac Bashevis Singer 1968)
In many cases we do not do what we will but we will what we do. (Modern
Neuroscience)
In the 60s
the brain surgeon Bertram Feinstein allows his friend Benjamin Libet to perform
experiments with uncovered brains. In the breaks during Feinstein’s surgical
work Libet amused the patients by performing simple experiments with electrical
stimulations of certain brain areas, and the patients had to report what they
felt. What is the inner experience of an outer stimulation? In some way, he
began to replicate Wilder Penfield’s investigations about topographic maps
(relating brain and body regions).
However, Libet's main interest was concentrated on the
time characteristics of the relation between external stimulus and
internal experience.
§
His first important finding was that it
needs at least a 500 ms cascade of electrical stimulation to
trigger a conscious experience.
§
In a later experiment Libet and his colleagues
found a very elegant experimental arrangement for investigating the timing of external
stimulus and internal experience:
Libet et al. (1979):
Subjective Referral of the Timing for a Conscious Sensory Experience. Brain
102, 193-224.
More or less simultaneously the experimenter
(1) stimulated a brain region such that the subject felt a tickle in her left
hand.
(2) stimulated the right hand directly.
The subject had to decide where she felt the stimulation first, in the right
hand or in the left hand or at the same time. It was possible for the
experimenter to shift the onsets of the stimulations
Libet’s expectation was that that in each case approximately a half second is
necessary to prompt a conscious experience (since it needs always approximately
a half second before a stimulation can trigger conscious experience). However,
the outcome was completely unexpected:
The stimulation of the brain and the stimulation of the skin were experienced
simultaneously if the stimulation of the brain started a half second earlier!
Conclusion
In case of the external stimulation of the skin our
'conscious mind' it subtracts a half second and predates subject's conscious
experience. In this way, we experience the outer world in the correct
way. It takes a while until we experience a event in the outer world.
However, our 'conscious mind' dates it back and we think we experience the
world in the temporally right moment. (The same phenomenon as with the Blind
Spot: Our perceptual system is insufficient. However, we do not become aware
of its errors)
Replication
A direct test of this hypothesis is possible if the incommensurability
of the two stimuli (i.e., the direct stimulation of the brain and the
stimulation of the skin) can be overcome. In the critical experiment two
different regions of the brain were stimulated electrically:
(1) a brain region of the cortex such that the subject felt a tickle in her
left hand.
(2) a brain region in the thalamus (phylogenetically old; so-called unspecific
system; this system collects information from the whole body and sends it to
the cortex)
The finding was that in this case very the same pattern is occurring:
The question of free will goes to the root of
our views about human nature and how we relate to the universe and to natural
laws.
§
Are we completely defined by
the deterministic nature of physical laws? Are we essentially sophisticated
automatons only, with our conscious feelings and intentions tacked on as
epiphenomena with no causal power? (cf. Thomas H.Huxley)
§
Or do we have some
independence in making choices and actions, not completely determined by the
known physical laws?
What we need first for approaching the problem in a experimental way is a good operational definition of free will. This approach should be in accord with common views.
That means
§
There should be no external control or cues to
affect the occurrence or emergence of the voluntary act under study; i.e. it
should be endogenous.
§
The subject should feel that he/she wanted to
do it, on her/his own initiative, and feel he could control what is being done,
when to do it or not to do it.
Many actions lack this second attribute. For example, when the primary motor
area of the cerebral cortex is stimulated, muscle contractions can be produced
in certain sites in the body. However, the subject (a neurosurgical patient)
reports that these actions were imposed by the stimulator, i.e. that he did not
will these acts. Clinical disorders with a similar effect are Parkinson and
even obsessive compulsions to act.
Simple examples of 'self
paced' voluntary acts are lifting a finger, closing an eye etc.
How
can we measure the onset of such a voluntary act?
This question is the most important for performing serious experiments.
Obviously, consciousness is private. It is a primary phenomenon. That means
consciousness is only accessible to the subject that has the experience.
(The only criterion for consciousness is consciousness itself). There is
principally no way to reduce it to some measurable activities in he brain. Of
course, there may be a correlation between consciousness and electrical
activity in the brain. However, the primary phenomenon of consciousness is
purely subjective.
Wund's clock
Consider the following two description of the same situation, one time as our subjective report, the other time as from the perspective of modern neuroscience.
|
A Subjective report |
In 1965, Hans
H. Kornhuber and Lüder Deecke investigated the correlation between
arbitrary movements of hand and foot and electrical activities in the brain
(EEG). The general question was this: It is possible to demonstrate by EEG that
a person performs a certain action (for example, she opens or closes her
hand). Kornhuber & Deecke found a rather strange phenomenon:
already 1 second before the hand (or foot) is moved an activity in the EEG
appears. They called it "Bereitschaftspotential" (readiness
potential). Surprising is that the readiness potential starts so early.
Readiness
Potential: Changes of the electrical field of a certain brain region
already 1 second before an action begins.
Benjamin Libet from the Medical centre of the
University of California (San Francisco) was fascinated by this finding and
asked a very important question: If a simple action like moving our hand is prepared
for more than a half second in our brain, at what moment do we consciously
decide to perform this action? Intuitively, we feel it is much less that a half
second. If this is right, and the preparation of an action begins much earlier
as the conscious decision to perform this action, can we have a free will then.
What about the freedom of our will?
The first experiments to address the timing of decisions directly were conducted by Benjamin Libet and his colleagues.
Libet et al. (1983): Time of conscious intention to act in relation
to onset of cerebral activity (readiness potential): the unconscious initiation
of a freely voluntary act. Brain 106, 623–642.
Their experiments asked questions about
when people believed they made a decision versus when the brain began to make
the decision. In one form of their experiment, they measured EEG activity while
subjects voluntarily chose to lift a finger. During the task, subjects watched
a rapidly moving clock hand and made a mental note of when they decided to lift
their finger.
This yielded three types of data:
(1)
when the subject lifted her finger [electromyogram of the muscles]
(2) when she believed she decided to lift her finger [Wund's clock]
(3) what her brain activity was during this time. [EEG]
The EEG results demonstrated that the cortex became active with a ‘readiness
potential’ 350 ms before the reported awareness of a ‘wish to move’. These
experiments suggested that our subjective awareness of decisions occurs
measurably later than the actual events of deciding
Our brain
initiates a 'voluntionary act' unconsciously. Not a conscious decision
but unconscious processes are at the beginning. This conclusions directly
contradicts our (conscious) common sense: Consciousness is unfaithful. It
swindles people. Furthermore, from the voluntionary act to the action (lifting
a finger) it takes about 200 ms (myogram of the muscles). Is this enough time
for a conscious stop of the action?
§
Actually, only 100 ms is
available in which the conscious function might affect the final outcome of the
volitional process (the primary motor cortex needs some time to the spinal
motor nerve cells).
§
Libet argues that this is
enough time for stopping or voting the final progress of the volitional
process. "Conscious-will could thus affect the outcome of the volitional
process even though the latter was initiated by unconscious cerebral
processes."
§
Indirect evidence of a veto
possibility: Subjects in Libet's experiment reported that a conscious wish
appeared but that they suppressed or vetoed that. Libet could show that in such
cases a large readiness potential proceeded the veto, signifying that the
subject was indeed preparing the act, even thought the action was aborted by
the subject.
§
Does the conscious veto have
a preceding unconscious origin? In this case we cannot consider the veto
as action of free will. Libet proposes, instead, that the conscious veto
may not require preceding unconscious processes. The conscious veto is a control
function different from a conscious wish to act. At the moment there is no
experimental evidence against this possibility.
§
Psychological implication:
Consciousness is not a high level authority that gives orders to subordinated
instances. Instead, its main role is a selective one: make a decision
between the bulk of possibilities that are proposed by unconscious
processes.
§
Ethical implication: The role
of conscious free will is not to initiate a voluntary act, but rather to
control whether the act takes place. "This kind of role for free
will is actually in accord with religious and ethical strictures. These
commonly advocate that you 'control yourself'. Most of the Ten Commandments are
'do not' orders"
Libet investigated the relation between the
felt time of conscious actions/events and the time course of brain activity
(a). Another important question concerns the perception of events in time
dependent on the real time course, for example the timing judgment of
pressing a key and the (delayed) occurrence of a tone (b).
An especially interesting question concerns the interaction of time and
causality. What is the relation between time and causality? Does our perception
of when an event occurs depend on whether we caused it? A recent study by
Haggard, Clark and Kalogeras (2002) suggests that when we perceive our actions
to cause an event, it seems to occur earlier than if we did not cause it
(cf. David M. Eagleman and Alex O. Holcombe, in the reader)
In one condition, subjects judged the timing of an auditory tone by reporting
the corresponding position of a rapidly moving clock hand. In the second,
crucial condition, subjects pressed a key that caused a tone to follow 250 ms
later. Again, subjects judged the time of the tone. Comparing the data across
conditions, the perceived times of the tone when keypress and ton were causally
linked were compared with the conditions in which the ton occurred by itself.
Remarkably, when the tone was causally linked to the subjects’ keypress,
subjects judged the tone to occur 46 ms earlier than if these events had
occurred alone.
In a second experiment with different subjects, the delay between the keypress
and subsequent tone was varied (to be 250, 450, or 650 ms), and subjects judged
the time of the tone. Haggard et al. found that the further apart the keypress
and tone, the more the temporal ‘attraction’ of the tone to the keypress was
diminished (see Figure).
Conclusion
Tones perceived to be a consequence of one’s actions seem to occur earlier in
time than solitary tones. More generally, when we perceive our actions to cause
an event, it seems to occur earlier than if we did not cause it.
Eagleman & Holcombe's explanation
The philosopher David Hume pointed out that events that are close together in
space and time are more likely than spatio-temporally distant events to be
perceived as causally related. With certain assumptions about the prior
probabilities, it follows from Bayes’ equation that events known
to be causally related are more likely to be close in time and space than
unrelated events.
P(Cause (e1, e2) | CloseTime(e1, e2)) >
P(Cause (e1, e2) | DistantTime(e1, e2))
==> (with certain assumptions about the prior probabilities)
P(CloseTime(e1, e2) | Cause (e1, e2)) >
P(DistantTime(e1, e2) | Cause (e1, e2))